Thursday, July 9, 2020
Sovereignty and Lycanthropy in The Duchess of Malfi - Literature Essay Samples
ââ¬ËAs one judge said to the other, ââ¬Å"Be just, and if you canââ¬â¢t be just, be arbitrary.â⬠ââ¬â¢ William Burroughs Agambenââ¬â¢s Homo Sacer begins thus: ââ¬ËThe paradox of sovereignty consists in the fact the sovereign is, at the same time, outside and inside the juridical order.ââ¬â¢ This liminal space of sovereignty is diagnosed by Carl Schmitt: ââ¬ËAuthority proves that to produce law it need not be based on law.ââ¬â¢ Agambenââ¬â¢s case in Homo Sacer is that the ââ¬Ëinclusive exclusionââ¬â¢ that constitutes the sovereignââ¬â¢s legal status bears a striking similarity to a figure in Roman law who ââ¬Ëmay be killed and yet not sacrificed ââ¬â¢, the homo sacer, or as he appears in Germanic law, the Wolf-Man: ââ¬ËThe sovereign is the one with respect to whom all men are potentially homines sacri, and homo sacer is the one with respect to whom all men act as sovereigns.ââ¬â¢ It is with respect to Agambenââ¬â¢s theory of sovereignty that this essay will attempt to analyze the Wolf-Man of Websterââ¬â¢s The Duchess of Malfi, Ferdinand, whilst also attemptin g to map Websterââ¬â¢s critique of aristocracy by comparison with Nick Landââ¬â¢s analysis of the 15th century child murderer and noble, Gilles de Rais. ââ¬ËThe foundation of sovereign power is to be sought not in the subjectsââ¬â¢ free renunciation of their natural right but in the sovereigns preservation of his natural right to do anything to anyone.ââ¬â¢ The natural right to which Agamben refers here is nothing less than sovereignty itself, which Agamben claims finds its origin in the Hobbesian state of nature, the war of all against all in which ââ¬Ëman is a wolf to menââ¬â¢. Ferdinand reflects this in the curious lycanthropic analogy he draws between himself and his victims: ââ¬ËBosola: Alas, how have these [the Duchessââ¬â¢ children] offended? / Ferdinand: The death of young wolves is never to be pitiedââ¬â¢. Here we see Ferdinand, by his abuse of sovereignty, producing his own inhumanity in the dehumanization he inflicts, culminating in his total lycanthropisation and, ultimately, in his bringing about a microcosm of the Hobbesian state of nature through his mass-production of homines sacri in the chaot ic free-for-all of Act V. The only character in Act V who does not, in fact, employ either violence or deceit to achieve their ends is Antonio, who is killed by Bosola when Bosola immediately assumes he is an enemy (an almost reasonable assumption in the war of all against all). The following scene of mutual slaughter becomes almost farcically Hobbesian when Ferdinand attacks the Cardinal, assuming, unprovoked, that he is betrayed; ââ¬ËFerdinand: The devil! My brother fight upon the adverse party! [He wounds the CARDINAL]ââ¬â¢. The end of the play, however, seems to curiously diverge from this fervent critique of sovereignty when Delio announces that, by the installation of Antonioââ¬â¢s son as Duke, the social order is restored by bourgeois sovereignty: ââ¬ËDelio: These wretched eminent things leave no more fame behind emâ⬠¦ Integrity of life is fames best friend, which nobly, beyond death, shall crown the end.ââ¬â¢ Websterââ¬â¢s case here seems to be not against sovereignty as such, but rather against the aristocratic juridical system alone. Whether Websterââ¬â¢s optimism towards bourgeois sovereignty is misguided is a matter we will return to later, but Websterââ¬â¢s distinction between the moral psychology of aristocratic and bourgeois sovereignty does, however, present us with another lens to view the lupine tendencies of our Duke through: the lens of Medieval warfare. In his essay ââ¬ËAfter the Lawââ¬â¢ Nick Land seeks to present the case of Gilles de Rais through the fundamental disjunction between the bourgeois ââ¬Ërelentless refusal of sumptuary consumptionââ¬â¢ and the pre-modern ââ¬Ëreckless militarism of the French aristocracyââ¬â¢. De Raisââ¬â¢ sumptuary habits aligned him firmly, even anachronistically, with his aristocratic heritage (ââ¬ËEven by the standards of his times and rank, de Rais dissipated vast tranches of his wealth with abnormal extravaganceââ¬â¢) , which Land connects to the aristocratic concept of sovereignty, quoting from Bataille: ââ¬ËAccumulated wealth has nothing but subordinate value, but wealth that is wasted or destroyed has, to the eyes of those who waste it, or destroy it, sovereign valueââ¬â¢. We must focus on the dual meaning of the word ââ¬Ësovereignââ¬â¢ here as not only representing voluptuosity as the sacred purpose of wealth, but also the sense in which voluptuosity is the act of a sovereign, one who may waste the production of others through their thirst for destruction, their ââ¬Ëwolfish desireââ¬â¢. A connection between aristocratic militarism and this wolfish desire pervades The Duchess of Malfi. When Castruccio expresses a bourgeois, utilitarian attitude to the idea of warrior nobles (ââ¬ËIt is fitting a soldier arise to be a prince, but not necessary a prince descend to be a captainâ⬠¦ He were far better to do it by deputy.ââ¬â¢) Ferdinand responds with total disdain for what is ââ¬Ënecessaryââ¬â¢, or indeed ââ¬Ëbetterââ¬â¢ by these measured standards, saying: ââ¬ËWhy should he not as well sleep or eat by a deputy? This might take idle, offensive, and base office from him, whereas the other deprives him of honour.ââ¬â¢ The similarities to de Rais continue here: ââ¬ËTo the eyes of Gilles war is a gameââ¬â¢ and ââ¬Ëneither intelligence nor calculation is nobleââ¬â¢. In short, ââ¬Ëwar exceeds judgementââ¬â¢ , both in the sense of utilitarian value judgement and moral juridical judgement. But, despite the clear differences between the aristocratic and the bourgeois attitude to voluption, what we see is not merely an aristocratic wolfish desire coincident with sovereignty, but rather a sovereignty which produces wolfish desire. While Webster expresses optimism at the new bourgeois order and exalts in the just downfall of aristocracy, Land instead sees the case of damned aristocrats as a tragedy of dates: ââ¬ËThe tragedy of de Raisâ⬠¦ was that of living the transition from sumptuary to rational sociality.ââ¬â¢ In light of this it makes sense to ask whether it is aristocracy which should be on trial, or sovereignty itself. Websterââ¬â¢s ââ¬Ëtrialââ¬â¢ of Ferdinand, through the presentation of his downfall, effectively presents the case of aristocratic sovereignty on trial in the court of bourgeois sovereignty. Seeming to predict Charles I legal defense at Westminster Hall (ââ¬ËI would know by what power I am called hither, by what lawful authority?ââ¬â¢ ) Ferdinandââ¬â¢s apology of himself consists not in arguing the facts of his crimes those are incontestable but rather the legitimacy of the sovereignty that calls him into question: ââ¬ËWhat I have done, I have done: Ill confess nothingââ¬â¢, and this is for good reason; Ferdinandââ¬â¢s crimes stem entirely from his sovereignty. His bloodlust, like de Raisââ¬â¢, is merely the expression of the purpose of feudal sovereignty vis-a-vis the sovereign value of wealth: voluptuosity. Additionally, in Duchess we see sovereignty only ever mobilized in its capacity to lupinize both the wielder at the victim: sovereignty is not on ly the tool by which Ferdinand enacts his wolfish desire, but the engine of its production. His crimes are therefore, in a sense, not his own, since they are only enacted through him by sovereignty, the same power which, in its bourgeois manifestation, now accuses him. It is for this reason that Land refers to Ferdinandââ¬â¢s counterpart, de Rais, as ââ¬Ëthe pale criminalââ¬â¢, referencing Nietzscheââ¬â¢s Thus Spoke Zarathustra . The pale criminal is driven to murder by an engine of desire beyond his control: ââ¬Ëhis soul wanted blood, not robbery.ââ¬â¢ , and thus he stands accused of a crime which exceeds him. Similarly, Webster does not put sovereignty on trial in The Duchess of Malfi, but by exalting in the victory of the bourgeois order over the aristocratic, instead celebrates a new form of sovereignty. It seems Webster hears, but does not appreciate Nietzscheââ¬â¢s warning about the changeability of sovereign ideologies: ââ¬Ëthere have been other ages a nd another evil and goodââ¬â¢ Works Cited Agamben, Giorgio, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (California: Stanford University Press, 1998) Burroughs, William, Naked Lunch, (New York: Grove Press, 2002) Carlton, Charles, Charles I: The Personal Monarch, 2nd edn (London: Routledge, 1995) Land, Nick, ââ¬ËAfter the Lawââ¬â¢, Fanged Noumena, ed. by Robin Mackay Ray Brassier (Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2018) Webster, John, The Duchess of Malfi, in The Norton Anthology of English Literature, ed. by Stephen Greenblatt, 10th edn, 6 vols (New York: W. W. Norton Company, Inc., 2018), II
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)